Abstract
By the time Hume started to work on his Treatise, the notion of an idea as the primary, most general sort of mental item dominated European philosophy. Although Descartes noted that, strictly speaking, only those “thoughts that are as it were images of things” were appropriately described as ideas, in practice he used “the word ‘idea’ to refer to whatever is immediately perceived by the mind.” Not only do we have ideas of trees and the sun, but we also have ideas of our own activities of thinking and willing. Locke characterizes “idea” as “being that Term, which, I think, serves best to stand for whatsoever is the Object of the Understanding when a Man thinks.” Locke also thinks that we not only have ideas that derive from things or objects in the world (ideas of sensation), but also of the activities and operations of our own minds (ideas of reflection). Ideas of sensation are acquired through the operation of external objects on our sense organs, while ideas of reflection come from introspection, from thinking about what happens within our own minds. He also thinks that these ideas of reflection are of two basic sorts of mental activity, perception and willing, that correspond to two faculties of mind: the understanding (or the power of thinking) and the will (or the power of volition).
Original language | English (US) |
---|---|
Title of host publication | The Cambridge Companion to Hume |
Subtitle of host publication | Second Edition |
Publisher | Cambridge University Press |
Pages | 70-104 |
Number of pages | 35 |
ISBN (Electronic) | 9781139001991 |
ISBN (Print) | 9780521859868 |
DOIs | |
State | Published - Jan 1 2008 |
ASJC Scopus subject areas
- General Arts and Humanities